|
Books > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
Edited by a renowned scholar in the field, this anthology provides
an extensive and varied collection of classical and contemporary
readings in the philosophy of mind. Especially noteworthy are the
substantial authoritative introductions to each section, which set
extracts in context and guide the reader through them. The volume
is organised into 12 sections, providing instructors with
flexibility in designing and teaching a variety of courses. It
contains 50 important writings on the philosophy of mind, with
introductions to each section, discussion questions and guides to
further reading. Perfect for undergraduate courses, this book
offers the ideal, self-contained introduction to the philosophy of
mind.
This book discusses the influence of creative work on human life,
and the role it has played in shaping human civilization since
antiquity. To do so, it analyzes the history of thought on creative
work from three civilizations: Greek, Indian, and Chinese, as well
as contemporary neurological studies on consciousness. According to
the classical Greeks, humans are instinctively predisposed to use
creative work to gain truth, wisdom and happiness; the Indians
consider that Dharma (duty, morality, etc.) can be achieved only
through work (karma); and for the Chinese, creative work is needed
to attain the supreme wisdom (Dao). Modern studies on consciousness
show that our brain creates a personal self-model (ego tunnel) when
we learn things creatively, and developing such skills provides
lifelong protection for the brain. In the 21st century, human
involvement in creative work is declining as we use mechanized
systems to gain more and more profit, but the wealth falls into the
hands of the few superrich: the Plutonomy. As creative work is
taken over by AI systems, human work is reduced to operating those
machines, and this in turn leads to an exponential growth in the
number of part-time workers (Precariat). The declining value of
human life today is a consequence of this change in society.
Further, reducing creative work means we have no way to distribute
wealth, nor do we have any means to address problems like the lack
of enthusiasm in the young; the health crisis due to lack of
physical activity; or the environmental crisis due to the high
demand for energy to run mechanized systems. This book explores
these issues.
Danish Yearbook of Philosophy - Volume 27
Comparative psychology, the multidisciplinary study of animal
behavior and psychology, confronts the challenge of how to study
animals we find cute and easy to anthropomorphize, and animals we
find odd and easy to objectify, without letting these biases
negatively impact the science. In this Element, Kristin Andrews
identifies and critically examines the principles of comparative
psychology and shows how they can introduce other biases by
objectifying animal subjects and encouraging scientists to remain
detached. Andrews outlines the scientific benefits of treating
animals as sentient research participants who come from their own
social contexts and with whom we will be in relationship. With
discussions of science's quest for objectivity, worries about
romantic and killjoy theories, and debates about chimpanzee
cognition between primatologists who work in the field and those in
the lab, Andrews shows how scientists can address the different
biases through greater integration of the subdisciplines of
comparative psychology.
This book explores the important yet neglected relationship between
the philosophy of time and the temporal structure of perceptual
experience. It examines how time structures perceptual experience
and, through that structuring, the ways in which time makes
perceptual experience trustworthy or erroneous. Sean Power argues
that our understanding of time can determine our understanding of
perceptual experience in relation to perceptual structure and
perceptual error. He examines the general conditions under which an
experience may be sorted into different kinds of error such as
illusions, hallucinations, and anosognosia. Power also argues that
some theories of time are better than others at giving an account
of the structure and errors of perceptual experience. He makes the
case that tenseless theory and eternalism more closely correspond
to experience than tense theory and presentism. Finally, the book
includes a discussion of the perceptual experience of space and how
tenseless theory and eternalism can better support the problematic
theory of naive realism. Philosophy of Time and Perceptual
Experience originally illustrates how the metaphysics of time can
be usefully applied to thinking about experience in general. It
will appeal to those interested in the philosophy of time and
debates about the trustworthiness of experience.
Intentionality is the mind's ability to be "of," "about," or
"directed" at things, or to "say" something. For example, a thought
might "say" that grass is green or that Santa Claus is jolly, and a
visual experience might be "of" a blue cup. While the existence of
the phenomenon of intentionality is manifestly obvious, how exactly
the mind gets to be "directed" at things, which may not even exist,
is deeply mysterious and controversial. It has been long assumed
that the best way to explain intentionality is in terms of tracking
relations, information, functional roles, and similar notions. This
book breaks from this tradition, arguing that the only empirically
adequate and in principle viable theory of intentionality is one in
terms of phenomenal consciousness, the felt, subjective, or
qualitative feature of mental life. According to the theory
advanced by Mendelovici, the phenomenal intentionality theory,
there is a central kind of intentionality, phenomenal
intentionality, that arises from phenomenal consciousness alone,
and any other kind of intentionality derives from it. The
phenomenal intentionality theory faces important challenges in
accounting for the rich and sophisticated contents of thoughts,
broad and object-involving contents, and nonconscious states.
Mendelovici proposes a novel and particularly strong version of the
theory that can meet these challenges. The end result is a
radically internalistic picture of the mind, on which all
phenomenally represented contents are literally in our heads, and
any non-phenomenal contents we in some sense represent are
expressly singled out by us.
Maps out how new developments in 21st-century philosophy intersect
with the study of literature This forward-thinking, non-traditional
reference work uniquely maps out how new developments in 21st
century philosophy are entering into dialogue with the study of
literature. Going beyond the familiar methods of analytic
philosophy, and with a breadth greater than traditional literary
theory, this collection looks at the profound consequences of the
interaction between philosophy and literature for questions of
ethics, politics, subjectivity, materiality, reality and the nature
of the contemporary itself.
Truth is one of the central concepts in philosophy, and has been a
perennial subject of study. Michael Glanzberg has brought together
36 leading experts from around the world to produce the definitive
guide to philosophical issues to do with truth. They consider how
the concept of truth has been understood from antiquity to the
present day, surveying major debates about truth during the
emergence of analytic philosophy. They offer critical assessments
of the standard theories of truth, including the coherence,
correspondence, identity, and pragmatist theories. They explore the
role of truth in metaphysics, with lively discussion of
truthmakers, proposition, determinacy, objectivity, deflationism,
fictionalism, relativism, and pluralism. Finally the handbook
explores broader applications of truth in philosophy, including
ethics, science, and mathematics, and reviews formal work on truth
and its application to semantic paradox. This Oxford Handbook will
be an invaluable resource across all areas of philosophy.
Oxford Studies in Metaphysics is the forum for the best new work in
this flourishing field. OSM offers a broad view of the subject,
featuring not only the traditionally central topics such as
existence, identity, modality, time, and causation, but also the
rich clusters of metaphysical questions in neighbouring fields,
such as philosophy of mind and philosophy of science. Besides
independent essays, volumes will often contain a critical essay on
a recent book, or a symposium that allows participants to respond
to one another's criticisms and questions. Anyone who wants to know
what's happening in metaphysics can start here.
The human world is in a mess. The human mind is in a mess. And now
the human species is threatening its own survival by its own
inventions and by war. For thousands of years, human beings
conducted a great debate about the human condition and human
possibilities, about philosophy and society and law. In 1516,
Thomas More, in his book Utopia, contributed to the ancient debate,
at another time of profound transformation in the human world. In
our own time, we have witnessed a collapse in intellectual life,
and a collapse in the theory and practice of education. The old
debate is, for all practical purposes, dead. In 2016, Philip
Allott's Eutopia resumes the debate about the role of philosophy
and society and law in making a better human future, responding to
a human world that More could not have imagined. And he lets us
hear the voices of some of those who contributed to the great
debate in the past, voices that still resonate today.
The extraordinary breadth and depth of Leibniz's intellectual
vision commands ever increasing attention. As more texts gradually
emerge from seemingly bottomless archives, new facets of his
contribution to an astonishing variety of fields come to light.
This volume provides a uniquely comprehensive, systematic, and
up-to-date appraisal of Leibniz's thought thematically organized
around its diverse but interrelated aspects. Discussion of his
philosophical system naturally takes place of pride. A cluster of
original essays revisit his logic, metaphysics, epistemology,
philosophy of nature, moral and political philosophy, and
philosophy of religion. The scope of the volume, however, goes
beyond that of a philosophical collection to embrace all the main
features of Leibniz's thought and activity. Contributions are
offered on Leibniz as a mathematician (including not only his
calculus but also determinant theory, symmetric functions, the
dyadic, the analysis situs, probability and statistics); on Leibniz
as a scientist (physics and also optics, cosmology, geology,
physiology, medicine, and chemistry); on his technical innovations
(the calculating machine and the technology of mining, as well as
other discoveries); on his work as an 'intelligencer' and cultural
networker, as jurist, historian, editor of sources and librarian;
on his views on Europe's political future, religious toleration,
and ecclesiastical reunification; on his proposals for political,
administrative, economic, and social reform. In so doing, the
volume serves as a unique cross-disciplinary point of contact for
the many domains to which Leibniz contributed. By assembling
leading specialists on all these topics, it offers the most rounded
picture of Leibniz's endeavors currently available.
Heidegger's Moral Ontology offers the first comprehensive account
of the ethical issues that underwrite Heidegger's efforts to
develop a novel account of human existence. Drawing from a wide
array of source materials from the period leading up to the
publication of Being and Time (1919-1927), and in conversation with
ancient, modern, and contemporary contributions to moral
philosophy, James D. Reid brings Heidegger's early philosophy into
fruitful dialogue with the history of ethics, and sheds fresh light
on such familiar topics as Heidegger's critique of Husserl, his
engagement with Aristotle, his account of mortality, the role
played by Kant in the genesis of Being and Time, and Heidegger's
early reflections on philosophical language and concepts. This
lively book will appeal to all who are interested in Heidegger's
early phenomenology and in his thought more generally, as well as
to those interested in the nature, scope, and foundations of
ethical life.
This is a new volume of original essays on the metaphysics of
quantum mechanics. The essays address questions such as: What
fundamental metaphysics is best motivated by quantum mechanics?
What is the ontological status of the wave function? Does quantum
mechanics support the existence of any other fundamental entities,
e.g. particles? What is the nature of the fundamental space (or
space-time manifold) of quantum mechanics? What is the relationship
between the fundamental ontology of quantum mechanics and ordinary,
macroscopic objects like tables, chairs, and persons? The volume
includes a comprehensive introduction with a history of quantum
mechanics and the debate over its metaphysical interpretation
focusing especially on the main realist alternatives.
The question of the proper role of metaphysics in philosophy of
science is both significant and contentious. The last few decades
have seen considerable engagement with philosophical projects aptly
described as "the metaphysics of science:" inquiries into natural
laws and properties, natural kinds, causal relations, and
dispositions. At the same time, many metaphysicians have begun
moving in the direction of more scientifically-informed
("scientistic" or "naturalistic") metaphysics. And yet many
philosophers of science retain a deep suspicion about the
significance of metaphysical investigations into science. This
volume of new essays explores a broadly methodological question:
what role should metaphysics play in our philosophizing about
science? These new essays, written by leading philosophers of
science, address this question both through ground-level
investigations of particular issues in the metaphysics of science
and by more general methodological inquiry.
Since the publication of the companion volume Researching Learning
in Virtual Worlds in 2010, there has been a growth not only in the
range and number of educational initiatives taking place in virtual
worlds, but also in the depth of analysis of the nature of that
education. Understanding Learning in Virtual Worlds reflects those
changes through a collection of chapters that are extended versions
of research presented at the second Researching Learning in Virtual
Environments conference (ReLIVE 11), an international conference
hosted by the Open University UK. Included in this book are
chapters that explore the philosophical and methodological
underpinnings of understanding learning in virtual worlds, identify
and analyse the factors that support learning in these
environments, and present case studies that demonstrate some of the
various ways in which virtual worlds can be applied to facilitate
learning and teaching. The links between learning in a virtual
world and learning in the physical world are made apparent
throughout, and the authors reveal how understanding learning in
one informs the other. Understanding Learning in Virtual Worlds is
an important book not only to those who teach in virtual worlds,
but to anyone for whom understanding learning, in all its forms, is
of interest.
Two controversial authors debate the nature and methods of science,
its dogmas, and its future. Rupert Sheldrake argues that science
needs to free itself from materialist dogma while Michael Shermer
contends that science, properly conceived, is a materialistic
enterprise; for science to look beyond materialist explanations is
to betray science and engage in superstition. Issues discussed
include: materialism and its role in science, whether belief in God
is compatible with a scientific perspective, and parapsychology.
Michael Shermer is Editor-in-Chief of "Skeptic "magazine and the
author of numerous books including "Skeptic."Rupert Sheldrake is a
biologist and author of ten books including his most recent,
"Science Set Free," which challenges scientific dogma.
In his new Preface E.O. Wilson reflects on how he came to write
this book: how "The Insect Societies" led him to write
"Sociobiology," and how the political and religious uproar that
engulfed that book persuaded him to write another book that would
better explain the relevance of biology to the understanding of
human behavior.
How do mental events such as choices and decisions lead to physical
action? The problem of mental causation is one of the most
important and intriguing philosophical issues of our time and has
been at the centre of debates in the philosophy of mind for the
past fifty years. In opposition to the recent wave of reductionist
theories, this book argues that it is possible to account for
mental causation within a nonreductive framework as it adopts a
broadly Davidsonian approach to mental causation: reasons cause
actions because they are identical to physical events. This work
then defends this approach from the frequently raised criticism
that it entails epiphenomenalism - the inefficacy of the mental.
Moreover, Mental Causation moves beyond Davidson's views by
reconsidering the question of whether reasons causally explain
actions, arguing in opposition to Davidson, that explanations
appealing to reasons represent a distinct category of explanation
from causal explanation. Essential reading for anyone interested in
debates about mental causation, this is an excellent text for
senior undergraduates, graduate students, and professional
philosophers.
In his latest collection of essays, author, physician and humanist
philosopher Raymond Tallis meditates on the complexity of human
consciousness, free will, mathematics, God and eternity. The
philosophical reflections are interrupted by the fiercely polemical
essay 'Lord Howe's Wicked Dream', in which Tallis exposes the
'institutionally corrupt' deception intended to destroy the NHS,
and the values that have created and sustained it.
The philosophical problem of identity and the related problem of
change go back to the ancient Greek philosophers and fascinated
later figures including Leibniz, Locke, and Hume. Heraclitus argued
that one could not swim in the same river twice because new waters
were ever flowing in. When is a river not the same river? If one
removes one plank at a time when is a ship no longer a ship? What
is the basic nature of identity and persistence? In this book,
Andre Gallois introduces and assesses the philosophical puzzles
posed by things persisting through time. Beginning with essential
historical background to the problem he explores the following key
topics and debates: mereology and identity, including arguments
from 'Leibniz's Law' the constitution view of identity the
'relative identity' argument concerning identity temporary identity
four-dimensionalism, counterpart and multiple counterpart theory
supervenience the problem of temporary intrinsics the necessity of
identity Indeterminate identity presentism criteria of identity
conventionalism about identity. Including chapter summaries,
annotated further reading and a glossary, this book is essential
reading for anyone seeking a clear and informative introduction to
and assessment of the metaphysics of identity.
|
You may like...
Kybalion, El
Tres Iniciados
Paperback
R243
R203
Discovery Miles 2 030
|